Mahmut Boyuneğmez
“It is the immediate task of philosophy, which
is in the service of history, to unmask self-estrangement in its unholy forms
once the holy form of human self-estrangement has been unmasked. Thus, the
criticism of Heaven turns into the criticism of Earth, the criticism of
religion into the criticism of law, and the criticism of theology into the
criticism of politics.”[1]
"What is called the spirit of the law is actually property"
(Linguet)[2]
"It is authority that makes the law, not truth" ("autoritas, non
veritas facit legem"). (Hobbes, Laviathan, Chapter 26)[3]
"Where there is society, there is law" ("Ubi societas, ibi
jus").
Introduction
Law is not just rules or legislation; the legal structure, as a subset of the
state, is also an organization of power through the legal practices and
relations it contains. The struggles between the capitalist class and the
proletariat and the dynamic equilibrium in power relations are reflected in
legal forms. For example, with the neoliberal form of capital accumulation, the
decline in the power and organizational strength of the proletariat in power
relations has been expressed in legal regulations.
"Law is a system or order of social relations
that aligns with the interests of the ruling class and maintains its systematic
power/violence."[4] In other words, legal norms are not neutral; legal
rules have ideological functions aimed at maintaining the power of the ruling
class and become operational through certain social relations/practices within
the legal structure. These rules are conditioned by social relations shaped by
inter-class struggles. Law is a form in which the policies developed on behalf of
the ruling class and which function to maintain the capitalist system of social
relations take on the form of legislation.
On the other hand, it is possible to make predictions
about the future of law after capitalism. However, the scope of these
predictions can only include the main lines of development. In terms of
content, the legal formations of the lived experiences of socialism have an
accumulation that can enlighten our path.
I. Function, formation and
development of law
"Rule and
order are a form by which society frees itself from mere arbitrariness and
randomness to ensure its permanence. Society achieves this form in the static
moments of the process of production and the corresponding social relations, by
constantly reproducing itself. If this formation has lasted over a certain
period of time, it is petrified as custom and tradition and eventually
sanctified as an explicit law. This rule and order are an indispensable element
of any mode of production that seeks to achieve social resilience and independence
from randomness and arbitrariness."[5]
Legal rules are a form of "perpetuating" and
reproducing social relations. Not all social relations are transformed into
legal forms. But in capitalist societies, law is one of the most comprehensive
social regulators. The legal structure, however, is not the only practice and functioning
that regulates and reproduces social relations.[6] The fetishism of law, in
other words, the view of law as the dominant or only structure that regulates
the social system, corresponds to an ideological inversion that is the result
of alienation.
Morality (ethics) is another ideological form that upholds
the order in social relations,[7] created in
reaction to the distortions and deviations in social relations. Morality
expresses hypocrisy; what gives rise to morality is the objectively ruthless,
unsympathetic, unscrupulous and merciless functioning of social relations and
their consequences.[8] As an ideology that functions in regulating social
relations, morality is related to law through the concepts of right and
justice.[9] Law, on the other hand, brings order to the conflicts and contentions
between subjects, irregularities and violations in social relations.
"At a certain,
very primitive stage of social development, the necessity arises for a common
order to govern social production, which is renewed day by day, and the
distribution and exchange of the products produced; the necessity arises for
the individual to subordinate himself to the common rules of production and
exchange. The set of rules, which at first remains a 'custom', soon becomes a
'law'. Alongside the law, organs to uphold it, public authority, i.e. the
'state', also emerges as a necessity.
"As society
develops further, the law evolves into a legal system, either limited or comprehensive
in scope. When this legal system becomes more complex, its terminology moves
away from that which expresses the ordinary economic conditions of social life.
This legal system appears as an independent entity that finds the reasons for
its existence and subsequent development not in the prevailing economic
conditions but in its own internal logic or, if you like, in the 'concept of
will'. People forget that their law derives from their economic conditions of
life, just as they forget that they are descended from animals.
"As the
legal system becomes a complex and comprehensive whole, a new social division
of labor becomes necessary; a class of professional jurists emerges and with
them the science of law."[10]
Constitutions, laws and regulations, which are legal
texts, owe their existence to social relations as rules that protect, regulate
and reproduce social relations. Factors such as historical heritage, the
composition of the dominant ideology, the level of development of economic
relations, the equilibrium of opposing class interests, and the international
conjuncture have an impact on the formation of legal texts. Legal concepts are
not abstract creations of the human mind, but concepts that reflect social
relations and reproduce these relations in the minds of professionals. Law
includes the rules by which social relations are reproduced and regulated
through the state. The state is the creator and enforcer of law.
"(...)
whatever class is in power, all the requirements of 'civil society' must also
be filtered through the will of the state in order to establish their universal
sovereignty in the guise of laws."[11]
Changes in social relations and differentiated needs,
as well as struggles for rights between classes, are important in the formation
of capitalist law during the establishment of the capitalist mode of
production. Once legal forms are established, their development continues:
"With the changing relations of life, laws inevitably change."[12]
“(...) the path
of the 'development of law' is limited, firstly, to the attempt to establish a
harmonious legal system and to eliminate the contradictions that would arise
from the direct transposition of economic relations into legal principles, and
secondly, to the recurrence of violations in this legal system under the
influence and compulsion of further economic developments that give rise to new
contradictions. (Here, for the time being, I am speaking only of civil
law)."[13]
II. Legal structure and rules
The legal dimension
of social relations includes relations with legal practices and norms (rules)
that regulate people's behavior/actions. Legal practices and relations are
constituted by the legal subset of the state, which is the organization of
political power (judicial processes in courts, prisons, etc.). Law, as one of
the superstructures, has a certain arrangement/organization
and functioning, in other words, structure.
In capitalist societies, the actions and transactions of individuals and corporates
are regulated by the legal structure. In the processes of regulating the behavior
and actions of individuals, organizations and institutions, the legal structure
constitutes an alienated (uncontrolled by people) dimension of power relations.
The legal structure is an organization of power that ensures people's loyalty
to political power through the state's practices of repression and coercion [14],
through the ideology of law and the ideological content of law itself, and
through its relation to the dominant moral conception of rights and justice in
society.
Instead of seeing law as a sphere/domain and tool of power
[15] of the ruling class, it should be understood as a dimension of the power relations between the capitalist class and
the working class and as a structuring
of these relations. In the legal dimension of power relations, ideological
values produced through legal practices are at work in addition to practices of
oppression/domination. Legal practices result not only in sanctions/oppression
but also in the establishment of ideological hegemony over people. The concept
of the "rule of law", the liberal ideological understanding that the
state and the law are neutral represent an ideological illusion in capitalist social formations. The "rule of
law", which means a state limited by law, has never existed as a reality
in social life, as evidenced, for example, by the existence of slush funds,
illegal secret service operations, and illegal activities of what is
misleadingly called the "deep state", but which are in fact carried
out by the main parts of the state.
Legal rules reproduce, regulate and protect social
relations. In capitalist societies, the dynamic interests of the capitalists,
the ruling class, are directly pursued in some branches of law created by the
state, for example in private law and labor law. Public law regulates the
relations between the state and the governed, as well as fundamental rights and
freedoms. Public law, like all law, is conditioned by the economic structure of
society. Criminal law, a branch of public law, guarantees the order and
functioning of social relations. The level of the proletariat's struggle is
reflected in capitalist law in general by the expression of certain rights in
the law or the exclusion of these rights from the law. Law, as a dimension and
structure of the rule/power of the capitalist class, can only survive if it
partially contains and meets the legal demands of the proletariat, the
oppressed and exploited class.
Ideological motifs in common sense, such as
traditional value judgments, moral criteria (e.g. justice, rights), non-moral
principles and values (e.g. equality, freedom) are massified and encapsulated
in legal rules. In the processes of transforming relations of production and
exchange into rules in the legal superstructure, mediation takes place through
various components of common sense or dominant ideology. Legal rules have ideological
contents and functions.
Legal legislation is hierarchical and largely
internally consistent. "In a modern state, law must not only correspond to
and be the expression of the general economic situation, but it must also be an
internally consistent expression of
it, which does not contradict itself by conforming to domestic
conflicts."[16]
When deciding in law, the "decision" is
formed by reasoning between facts and concepts rather than inferring from
rules. Formal logic is in force when examining illegality/legal conformity or
criminality.[17]
III. The ideological content and
function of law
In religions such as Christianity and Islam, even
though societies are predominantly composed of productive masses/workers, there
is an understanding of community or "ummah" that conceals this.
Individuals belonging to the exploiting and productive classes are preached to
be equal before God. Private and public law similarly recognizes that
individuals have equal rights and obligations and are equal before the law. Regardless
of the class they belong to, class differences are disregarded, and individuals
are legally considered through the abstraction of 'person'.[18] The legal
conceptualization of "person", which has its origins in the Roman law
"persona"[19] meaning the subject of rights, and equality before the
law are ideological assumptions. For example, the Turkish Constitution reads:
"Everyone is equal before the law without distinction as to language,
race, color, sex, political opinion, philosophical belief, religion, sect and
similar grounds."[20] On the other hand, the fact that the law uses the
conceptualization of "person" does not mean that it does not take
into account the differences between the parties to social relations in some
aspects. For example, legal rules regulating the relations between landlord and
tenant, seller and consumer, lender and borrower, boss and employee make
distinctions between the parties.[21]
Since it is a known reality that there are
inequalities and class differences between people, these assumptions of the law
are ideological mystifications. Moreover, in bourgeois legal theory/ideology,
it is assumed that the state represents the general will of the people, and
that citizens are people who live under state power by forming their
constitutions through a social contract. "General will" and
"social contract" are fantastical ideological concepts that serve to
perceive/make perceive social reality differently than it actually is. In the
existence and continuity of the capitalist nation-state, it is important that
the "nation", which is assumed to consist of equal citizens before
the law, is reproduced every day through various practices as a form of
ideological consciousness. By the way, the difference with the concept of
"people" is that it excludes exploiters and includes productive laborers.
Law protects and reproduces property relations, which
are the legal expression of social relations of production. Relations of
production, which are relations of exploitation, are legally guaranteed. While
the law of inheritance has no meaning for the working people, it ensures that
the property of the capitalist class, which exploits them, and also that of the
petty bourgeoisie, is passed down through generations. Private property
ownership is recognized as a right in the capitalist legal system. The recognition
of the freedom to own the means of production and the land is an ideological
recognition in accordance with capitalist relations of production.
Under socialism, housing, education, health, social
security are rights, and this is legally reflected in the constitution and
laws. Today, however, according to the capitalist class, these are not rights
and should be included in market relations as commodities and should be the
subject of buying and selling. In the neoliberal period, legislation was
revised/regulated in this direction and put into practice. Ideological
struggles over what rights are and are not, are reflected in legal regulations.
The liberal ideology's idea of negative freedom, i.e.
the understanding that individuals may not impose external restrictions on
their thoughts and actions provided that they do not harm others, is reflected
in legal rules. In practice, these freedoms are in most cases restricted.
Positive freedom, which means the ability of individuals to develop their
talents and potentials, to realize their strengths and to act in line with
their goals, is not taken into account in capitalist law. This is because for
these to be possible, individuals must have equality in their conditions and
access to opportunities, and they must be freed from alienated relations of production
and social relations.
Restrictions/prohibitions and penalties imposed on
freedom of thought, association and the freedom of the press and media, while
demonstrating the existence of the legal system as an organization/structure of
power, are also components of the ideological struggle of the capitalist class
to protect and maintain its hegemony over society.
IV. Law as a structure of hegemony
Althusser states that "Ideological State
Apparatuses" (ISA) exist and must be distinguished from "Repressive
Apparatuses of the State (RSA)."[22] Althusser's approach to
"Ideological State Apparatuses" (ISA) is problematic. According to
Althusser, the state is "present and at hand" in families with its
family ISA, in every school, whether private or public, with its educational
ISA, in the press-radio-television channels and even the internet with its
communication ISA, in literature, fine arts and sports with its cultural ISA,
in this field with its legal ISA, and in other fields of social life with other
ISAs. In short, for him, the state is almost everywhere or almost everything
(family, literature, etc.) is the state. Whether the state is considered as an
"apparatus" or as a "social relation" (which it should be),
it cannot exist in almost all processes, organizations and institutions of
society, even through ideology. All processes, organizations and institutions
of societies are not "apparatuses". Moreover, they cannot be
characterized as "apparatuses of the state".
In our view, the power of the capitalist class in
capitalist society is constituted and reproduced on a social scale. The social
power of the capitalist class is not achieved through the organization of the
state alone. There are also economic, ideological (educational, communicative),
cultural (literary, artistic, sportive), civil society organizational (unions,
associations, foundations, etc.) dimensions of social domination/power. In the
relationship established between workers and bosses on the scale of
enterprises, there is not only an economic and legal relationship, but also a
sovereignty-subordination relationship. The education system and the media
contain practices and interpersonal relations that participate in the formation
of the hegemony necessary for the social power of the capitalist class. Trade
unions, as corporatist organizations that reconcile the interests of the
working class with those of the state and the bosses, ensure the attachment of
workers to the capitalist system, and so on... We call the organizations that
participate in the formation of the social domination/power of the capitalist
class in all these dimensions and reproduce this domination/power every day,
the hegemony structures of social power.
Hegemony is realized through coercion, compulsion and forcing,
fear, intimidation, ideological approval, consent and attachment, distraction
and occupation. The social power of the capitalist class is ensured and
reproduced through hegemony. Through various social processes, organizations
and productions, the social domination/power of the capitalist class is
perpetuated.
As a hegemony organization/structure of the social
power of the capitalist class, law has both repressive functions (courts,
prisons, penal system) and ideological functions.
V. Is law 'relatively autonomous'?
According to Poulantzas, the state and law are
relatively autonomous from the economic sphere. According to him, in capitalist
society, the political is separated from the economic. In the production
process or in the sphere of circulation, productive laborers are not directly
subjected to political violence.[23] Poulantzas also mentions the relative
autonomy of the state vis-à-vis the ruling class, the bourgeoisie.[24] For
example, it is a reality that the majority of politicians and the bureaucracy
today are seperated from the capitalist class.
Even so, cultural and ideological hegemony over
workers is crucial for the reproduction of their labor power, that is, for
workers to be able to go back to work every next day. The sustainability of
capitalist relations of production, which are relations of exploitation, is
only possible when there is ideological hegemony over workers. Furthermore, the
relations of exploitation cannot be sustained without the possibility of
physical oppression in the case of dissent and without being forced to live and
work in the existing conditions of life as a result of the lack of
political/ideological alternatives. Workers cannot be exploited without the
existence of mechanisms of oppression and without being forced to work because
they have no alternative to work.
In our view, capitalism is a system of social
relations with economic, political, ideological, cultural, legal and
governmental dimensions, which are
not separate and isolated from each other, but intertwined and interacting. The
legal, state, ideological, political and cultural dimensions of social
relations are subject to the most general conditioning by the economic
structure/base. The different dimensions of social relations form a system/totality
and, moreover, the elements of this system/totality develop unevenly. The
economic dimension of social relations does not constitute an isolated
"level", an isolated "field" or "space"
externally related to other dimensions of social relations. The production of
social material life is ensured and sustained not only through economic
practices but also through various practices in different dimensions of social
relations.
The "relative autonomy" of the vast majority
of politicians and bureaucracy from the active capitalist class is an
appearance. In essence, politicians and bureaucrats, who are committed to
different shades of liberalism, the worldview of the bourgeoisie, or to various
sections of the dominant ideological spectrum, are engaged in political,
technical and ideological work to maintain the social power of the capitalist
class through their ideological commitments.
The apparent neutrality of law, as well as its
formalism and generality, cannot be taken as a sign of its relative autonomy
from labor-capital relations. This is because the rules and structure of law,
as a system, have the function of keeping the irreconcilable opposition of
labor and capital in a dynamic equilibrium, making oppositions tolerable and
softening them in order to prevent this opposition from turning into
contradictions.[25] Furthermore, struggles between classes affect the formation
of legal forms.
VI. Rights and justice
“Right can never be higher than the economic structure
of society and its cultural development conditioned thereby.”[26]
At different levels of development of social
relations, rights and ethical/moral values derived from these relations are
formed; they are widely recognized, adopted and given legal forms. Each social
formation has sovereign equity criteria, definitions of rights, and an
understanding of justice that is shaped according to the production structure
of the age in which it exists, and that is translated into ethical values and
legal expressions. The concepts of right and justice are moral and at the same
time legal concepts.
In each historical epoch, the condition of social
relations determines what rights are and what they encompass. In the Babylonian
Empire, the interests and rights of landowners, priests, merchants and
moneylenders were regulated by the laws of Hammurabi. The protection of the
rights of slaves in these laws is noteworthy. A slave is the absolute property
of his master; he can be sold, transferred, pledged. These are the rights of
the master. If the slave does not submit, the law gives the master the right to
mutilate him. In this society, even the two segments of free people (mushkinu
and amelu/maremelu), slaves and property owners, do not enjoy equal rights.
This situation is also regulated in the Hammurabi Code. In the Babylonian
Empire, the rural community of free agriculturalists was united by rights and
obligations related to irrigation. In the Spartan state, the social strata of
spartiates, perioikos and ilotes had different rights. In the Athenian slave
democracy, one-sixth to one-seventh of the population of Attica had rights;
slaves, women and chattels had no political rights.[27] In the Middle Ages,
feudal social relations imposed on serfs the obligation to pay the master's
right (cens). Feudal lords have the right of first night, the right to imprison
and torture serfs. In fact, feudal drudgery, tribute, taxes were all recognized
as the rights of feudal lords, high clergy, nobles and kings.[28]
"In most of
the states known to history, the rights granted to citizens have also varied
according to their wealth, a fact which clearly shows that the state is an
organization of the propertied class to protect against the propertyless class.
This was already the case in Athens and Rome for classes organized according to
wealth. This was the case in the medieval state, where political power was
organized hierarchically according to land ownership. This is also the case in
modern representative states, where a certain tax (cens electoral) is paid in
order to participate in elections. (...) The democratic republic, (this)
highest form of state, no longer formally recognizes distinctions of wealth. In
the democratic republic, wealth manifests its power in an indirect, but no less
secure way."[29]
With the development of capitalist relations of production,
new rights emerged.
"In
capitalist bourgeois society, privilege is replaced by law. When the right to
property is replaced by the right of every citizen to freely dispose of and
enjoy his property, his income, the products of his labor and industriousness,
and by the right of privileged land ownership, the right of free parcelling and
free contract arises."[30]
The liberal principle of freedom essentially refers to
the right to property. It is argued that this cannot be restricted. The
bourgeois citizen's right to own private property, the right to acquire and
dispose of wealth, is recognized as individual freedom. The right to security
is defined to protect the personality, rights and property of citizens, which
means the protection of the bourgeoisie against the rest of society. Recognized
as "inherent rights", these rights are reflected in moral values of
justice and also in laws. Marx identifies the origin of these rights in the
exchange of values, in other words, in exchange relations:
"This
sphere (the sphere of circulation or commodity exchange-MB), within the
boundaries of which the buying and selling of labor power goes on and on, was
in fact a paradise of man's inherent rights. Only Liberty, Equality, Property
and Bentham (the founder of utilitarianism-MB) dominate here. Freedom, because
both the buyer and seller of the commodity, say labor power, are only under the
influence of their own free will. They contract as free parties and the
agreement they reach is nothing but the legal expression of their common will.
Equality, because they relate to each other as simple commodity owners and
exchange equivalent values. It is property, because these parties dispose of
what is their property. And Bentham, because each party thinks only of itself.
The only force that brings them together and brings them into relation is
selfishness, gain and private self-interest."[31]
Conceptions of justice and rights involve ideological
judgments and values. But this does not mean that all of these understandings
necessarily serve to support the status quo. In other words, standards of
justice are intrinsic to societies, but since social relations involve opposing
tendencies, there is also an ideological dimension in which these tendencies
and the interests of revolutionary classes are reflected. The struggle of the
working class in capitalist society and its opposition to the status quo
provides the objective ground for socialist ideology to have critical values,
principles, and a conception of justice and rights. It is unthinkable for
socialists not to mention rights and justice in their struggles. The socialist
understanding of justice as a moral conceptualization does not at all require
them to remain neutral between people's interests.
"(...)
justice is nothing but a reflection of existing economic relations, sometimes
conservative, sometimes revolutionary, elevated to the level of ideology and glorified.
The Greek and
Roman conception of justice considered slavery just. The bourgeois conception
of justice of 1789, on the other hand, did not consider feudalism just and
wanted it to be abolished. In the eyes of the Prussian Junker (landowner), even
the miserable Kreisordnung (land reform) was contrary to eternal justice. Now,
the concept of 'eternal justice' is one of those concepts which varies not only
according to time and place, but also according to people, and which everyone
understands differently."[32]
In criticizing capitalist exploitation and its social
consequences, moral judgments from the perspective of a socialist society are
not superfluous and meaningless. Because the values of the society of the
future, the understanding of rights and justice, the principle of freedom, can
be foreseen today with our knowledge of the economic structure of this society.
The achievements of lived experiences of socialism and the limited rights won
in capitalist countries through the struggles of the working class also guide
the values and principles to be defended in political struggle.
VII. Changes in rights and law in
the neoliberal era
Since public services are subjected to
commodity/exchange relations in the neoliberal era, the state's relations with
citizens are changing, and public rights obtained through class struggles are
being eliminated. Health, education and social security are no longer
compulsory rights that must be met by the state when demanded, but are now
provided under market conditions.
The requirements of the neoliberal form of capital
accumulation determine the arrangement/organization and functioning of the
capitalist state, in other words its structure. The form of capital
accumulation is constituted by the class structure in a social formation and
the way that society articulates with international capitalism.[33] The capitalist
state, which functions in the creation, maintenance and protection of the
neo-liberal form of capital accumulation, has been restructured with changes in
its legal, ideological and political dimensions. As the organization of the
power relations between the capitalist class and the proletariat, the state has
broken the organization and power of the working class in this power
relationship and increased asymmetry, liquidated its social functions towards
the class, and acquired authoritarian features.
On the other hand, in the neoliberal era, the legal
system is being opened to market relations and a kind of privatization is
taking place. Through new methods such as arbitration, mediation, conciliation,
short trials, negotiation, and the hiring of judges, the jurisdiction of the
state is transferred to the private judicial market. The private judicial
system, which has turned into an economic sector, is replacing the national
courts, which are in the public interest. This has led to the development of law
firms, which are able to generate high revenues.[34]
VIII. Criticism of Pashukanis' law
theory
In the years following the publication of his General
Theory of Law and Marxism in 1924, until 1936, Pashukanis changed his views and
admitted that his original ideas were wrong.[35] Here we would like to evaluate
some of the views that Pashukanis put forward in this work.
Law cannot be seen as a superstructural reflection of solely
economic relations, for example exchange relations. Pashukanis' thesis that it
is exchange relations that constitute law is not correct. Pashukanis writes as
follows:
"Just as
the wealth of capitalist society manifests itself in the form of an incredible
accumulation of commodities, so society appears as an infinite collection of
legal relations. Exchange presupposes an economy divided into small units.
Relations between isolated private economic units are established by contracts.
The legal relation between subjects is nothing but the other side of the
relation between commodified products of labor."[36]
Private law reflects and regulates the economic
relations of society, as in examples such as Roman Private Law and the French
Civil Code (Code Napoléon). However, as can be seen from examples such as the
regulation of crimes and punishments, the law of organizations such as
associations and trade unions, the rules governing political life, and the law
of marriage and divorce, not all law corresponds to the reflection of economic
relations.
Pashukanis sees criminal law as "a derivative of
exchange relations":
"Insofar as
it represents a derivative of the basic form to which modern society is
subject, criminal law is part of the legal superstructure: the equivalent form
of exchange with all its consequences. The realization of these exchange
relations in criminal law is one aspect of the realization of the rule of law,
the ideal form of relations between independent and equal producers of
commodities who meet in the marketplace."[37]
However, his assessment of the historical development
of criminal law shows that this type of law is not a product/derivative of
exchange relations.[38]
Pashukanis is also wrong in arguing against the idea
that capitalist legal concepts will give way to new concepts under socialism as
a reflection of evolving social relations.
"It is said
that working class law must find other general concepts and that this search
should be the task of Marxist theory of law (...) This tendency looks very
revolutionary when it demands new general concepts for working-class law. But
in reality, they proclaim the immortality of the legal form and attempt to
abstract it from the specific historical conditions that allowed its full
development and to present it as capable of constant renewal. The extinction of
certain categories of bourgeois law (not this or that commandment, but certain
categories) does not in any way imply their replacement by new categories of
working-class law. (...) The extinction of bourgeois legal categories would
mean the extinction of law in general, the disappearance of the legal element
in human relations."[39]
The problem here is this: Why, when the bourgeois
categories of law are dying out, should law in general and en bloc also die
out?... Socialism, as a social formation, will give superstructural forms to
the relations it bears. Within the dynamism of socialist society, it will
gradually free the state from class/political determination and socialize it,
and transform law into scientific regulatory rules.
"It must be
borne in mind that morality, law and the state are forms of bourgeois society.
Even if the working class has to use these forms, this does not mean that they
will continue to develop with a socialist content. These forms cannot assimilate
socialist content; they will have to wither away in proportion as that content
is realized."[40]
However, moral values such as the pursuit of the
common good, belief in the brotherhood of man ("the brotherhood of man is
not an empty phrase, but a reality" (Marx, 1844 Manuscripts)), "not
doing to others what you would not want done to yourself", solidarity and
cooperation, altruism are some of the principles and values developed under
socialism. As the content of social relations changes, the forms of law and the
state will be transformed and their content will undergo a metamorphosis.
IX. Communism and law
With the political revolution, the capitalist state
and the organization of legal power will be dissolved. Under socialism, law
will be rebuilt together with the socialist state and will develop and expand
in scope with society. During the social revolution, law will also be used as a
means of suppressing old social relations and developing new social relations.
In the process of the fusion and dissolution of the state with social
organizations (the identification of the state with the public), law will be the
natural (not alienated) law of social relations. For example, private property
and contractual rights will cease to be rights, and the right to life, the
right to housing, the right to health, the right to education, the right to
organize, etc. will be constitutionally and legally guaranteed.
The right to consumer goods is conditioned by the
economic structure of a socialist society. Here the principle of "from
each according to his ability, to each according to his work" applies.
This right is still within the narrow bourgeois horizon and is imperfect.
Because it does not take into account the differences between people in terms
of their abilities, productivity and family structure. It does not take into
account people's needs. In fact, under socialism, that is, in the first phase
of communism, the rights to education, health care and housing are provided to
all producers and there is equality of access to them. The necessary social
funds are allocated for these. It must also be said that aid will be provided
to compensate for differences between the family structures of producers.
Nevertheless, it must be recognized that the standard of distribution
applicable to this first phase will depend on the socialist conditions of
production. This is the "fair" distribution standard of socialism.
Socialism has its own style of distribution and form of justice. Communist
society can quickly replace socialism if the process of world socialist
revolution does not fail, since the conditions for a worldwide society of
abundance exist today. Then the standard of distribution will also change and
will be based on the rule of "to each according to his needs".
Under socialism, there is the right to live in
prosperity, the right to subsistence (food, potable water, shelter, clothing,
basic medical care, a liveable environment, etc.) and security (not to be
killed, not to be attacked, etc.); the right to speak, organize and assemble;
the right to vote, to hold or leave political office and to participate in
decisions in all social/economic institutions of which individuals are a part;
the right to housing, the right to work, the right to education and health.
Under socialism there are principles of justice that govern and regulate social
relations. There is freedom of speech and assembly, freedom of conscience and
thought, the right and freedom to own individual means of consumption, the
right to be protected from arbitrary practices. There is maximum equality of
opportunity for individuals to hold various positions and equal participation
in decision-making in the institutions in which they participate. The rights of
people who are unable to work, people with disabilities are protected by
society. Children have the right to a quality and scientific education (free of
charge, of course). There is no discrimination between people (the right to
equal treatment). Under socialism, the principles of justice and rights in
practice will be reflected in laws and the constitution. Obligations such as
taxes and the duty of collective defence will also find legal expression.
Under communism, law will be transformed into
scientific rules regulating society and people's behavior, and its function of
exercising domination and establishing ideological hegemony will be lost. Under
communism, instead of definitions of crime
and punishment, there will be symptoms
that pose a danger to social relations and methods
to be applied against these symptoms to protect society.
"The
transformation of punishment from its compensatory character into a measure of
social defence and the re-education of socially dangerous individuals (...)
re-education would no longer be a simple 'judicial consequence' of a court
decision sanctioning any 'crime', but would become a fully autonomous social
function of a medical and educational nature. (...) The orderly application of
the principle of social defence does not require the creation of a separate collection of crimes (and legislatively
or judicially prescribed punitive
measures), but a clear definition of the symptoms indicating socially dangerous situations and a clear and
detailed elaboration of the methods
to be applied in each specific case to protect society."[41]
The withering away of law only means the disappearance
of domination and the ideological functions of law.[42] Under communism, law
does not disappear. Because "ubi societas, ibi jus" (where there is
society, there is law). In the transition from the period of socialism to the
communist world society, legal rules and structures undergo metamorphosis. When
people's needs are adequately met in the abundant society of communism, when
there is equality of access to all opportunities for all, when people have control
over their living conditions, that is, when they are free from alienation,
there is no point in talking about justice and rights. Law has no other
existence here except as a written record of the principles of the functioning
of society and as the scientific organizing principles of social relations.
REFERENCES
[1] Marx, Karl.
“Introduction to a Contribution to the Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of
Right.” Marxists Internet Archive. https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1843/critique-hpr/intro.htm.
Accessed May 1, 2025.
[2] Marx, Karl.
Capital, Volume 1. Ankara: Sol Yayınları, 2004.
[3] Yelkenci,
Taner. “Marxist-Leninist State Theory.” In Marxist Theory of State and Law
(Marksist Devlet ve Hukuk Teorisi), 90. Ankara: NotaBene Publications, 2013.
[4] Yelkenci,
Taner. “Marxist-Leninist State Theory.” In Marxist Theory of State and Law
(Marksist Devlet ve Hukuk Teorisi), 89. Ankara: NotaBene Publications, 2013.
[5] Marx, Karl.
MEW XXV, 801. Quoted in Serozan, Rona. Marx/Engels Devlet ve Hukuk Üzerine
[Marx/Engels on State and Law], 26–27. Ankara: Enki Yayınları, 2015.
[6]
Karahanoğulları, Onur. “Diyalektik Hukuk Bilimi Notları.” In Marxism and Law
(Marksizm ve Hukuk), 205. Istanbul: Yordam Kitap, 2018.
[7] Engels,
Friedrich. Anti-Dühring. Ankara: Sol Yayınları, 2003.
[8] Pashukanis,
Evgeny B. General Legal Theory and Marxism. Istanbul: Birikim Publications,
2002.
[9] Pashukanis,
Evgeny B. General Legal Theory and Marxism. Istanbul: Birikim Publications,
2002.
[10] Engels,
Friedrich. The Housing Question. Quoted in Serozan, Rona. Marx/Engels Devlet ve
Hukuk Üzerine, 27. Ankara: Enki Yayınları, 2015.
[11] Engels,
Friedrich. Ludwig Feuerbach and the End of Classical German Philosophy. Quoted
in Serozan, Rona. Marx/Engels Devlet ve Hukuk Üzerine, 28. Ankara: Enki
Yayınları, 2015.
[12] Marx, Karl.
“Speech at the Trial of the Committee of Democrats of the Rhine Region.” Quoted
in Serozan, Rona. Marx/Engels Devlet ve Hukuk Üzerine, 37. Ankara: Enki
Yayınları, 2015.
[13] Marx, Karl,
and Friedrich Engels. Selected Correspondence 2. Ankara: Sol Yayınları, 1996.
[14] Elster,
Jon. Making Sense of Marx. Quoted in Peffer, R. G. Marxism, Morality, and
Social Justice, 154. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2001.
[15]
Karahanoğulları, Onur. Marxism and Law (Marksizm ve Hukuk). Istanbul: Yordam
Kitap, 2018.
[16] Marx, Karl,
and Friedrich Engels. Selected Correspondence 2. Ankara: Sol Yayınları, 1996.
[17]
Karahanoğulları, Onur. Marxism and Law (Marksizm ve Hukuk). Istanbul: Yordam
Kitap, 2018.
[18] Yelkenci,
Taner. “Marxist-Leninist State Theory.” In Marxist Theory of State and Law
(Marksist Devlet ve Hukuk Teorisi), 94–95. Ankara: NotaBene Publications, 2013.
[19] “The Latin
word ‘persona’ means mask.” Hacettepe Hukuk Fakültesi Dergisi 7, no. 1 (2017):
141–56. https://dergipark.org.tr/en/download/article-file/504794.
Accessed May 1, 2025.
[20] Turkish
Constitution, Article 10. https://www5.tbmm.gov.tr/anayasa.htm.
Accessed May 1, 2025.
[21] Warrington,
Ronnie. “Pashukanis and the Theory of the Commodity Form.” In Marxist Theory of
State and Law (Marksist Devlet ve Hukuk Teorisi), 130. Ankara: NotaBene
Publications, 2013.
[22] Althusser,
Louis. Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses. Translated by Alp
Tümertekin. Istanbul: Ithaki Publications, 2003.
[23] Buckel,
Sonja. “The Legal Concentration of Power Relations: Nicos Poulantzas and Law.”
In Marxist Theory of State and Law (Marksist Devlet ve Hukuk Teorisi), 279–301.
Ankara: NotaBene Publications, 2013.
[24] Poulantzas,
Nicos. “The Problem of the Capitalist State.” In Selection of Contemporary
Marxism: Texts of the Century, edited by Bertell Ollman and Kevin B. Anderson,
316–28. London: Verso, 2019.
[25] Altvater,
Elmar, and Jürgen Hoffmann. “The State Derivation Debate in West Germany: The
Relationship between Economy and Politics as a Problem of Marxist State
Theory.” In Marxist Theory of State and Law (Marksist Devlet ve Hukuk Teorisi),
322. Ankara: NotaBene Publications, 2013.
[26] Marx, Karl.
Critique of the Gotha Program. Marxists Internet Archive. https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1875/gotha/ch01.htm.
Accessed May 1, 2025.
[27] Diakov, V.,
and S. Kovalev. Primeval History. Ankara: V Publications, 1987.
[28] Engels,
Friedrich. Peasants’ War. Ankara: Sol Yayınları, 1975.
[29] Engels,
Friedrich. The Origin of the Family, Private Property, and the State. Ankara:
Sol Yayınları, 1979.
[30] Marx, Karl,
and Friedrich Engels. The Holy Family. Quoted in Serozan, Rona. Marx/Engels
Devlet ve Hukuk Üzerine, 52. Ankara: Enki Yayınları, 2015.
[31] Marx, Karl.
Capital, Volume 1. Ankara: Sol Yayınları, 2004.
[32] Engels,
Friedrich. The Housing Question. Quoted in Serozan, Rona. Marx/Engels Devlet ve
Hukuk Üzerine, 27–28. Ankara: Enki Yayınları, 2015.
[33] Gülalp,
Haldun. Capitalism, Classes, and the State. Istanbul: Belge Yayınları, 1998.
[34] Gülhan,
İlhan. Retreating with the Counterrevolutionary Bourgeoisie (Karşıdevrimci
Burjuvazi ile Geriye Dönüş). Sendika.org, June 2023. https://sendika.org/2023/06/karsidevrimci-burjuvazi-ile-geriye-donus-686105/.
Accessed May 1, 2025.
[35] Reich,
Norbert. “Marxist Legal Theory Between Revolution and Stalinism: Pashukanis
Example.” In Marxist Theory of State and Law (Marksist Devlet ve Hukuk
Teorisi), 183–98. Ankara: NotaBene Publications, 2013.
[36] Pashukanis,
Evgeny B. General Legal Theory and Marxism. Istanbul: Birikim Publications,
2002.
[37] Pashukanis,
Evgeny B. General Legal Theory and Marxism. Istanbul: Birikim Publications,
2002.
[38] Pashukanis,
Evgeny B. General Legal Theory and Marxism. Istanbul: Birikim Publications,
2002.
[39] Pashukanis,
Evgeny B. General Legal Theory and Marxism. Istanbul: Birikim Publications,
2002.
[40] Pashukanis,
Evgeny B. General Legal Theory and Marxism. Istanbul: Birikim Publications,
2002.
[41] Pashukanis,
Evgeny B. General Legal Theory and Marxism. Istanbul: Birikim Publications,
2002.
[42] Karahanoğulları, Onur writes: “State and law are not eternal forms. The beginning of their withering away from human history is not the moment of revolution, nor can a date or stage be given for the day they will wither away. It is also possible for law to tend towards withering away within capitalism.” See Karahanoğulları, Onur. Marxism and Law (Marksizm ve Hukuk). Istanbul: Yordam Kitap, 2018, p. 231. In our view, state and legal structures/organizations will be “socialized” in the period of socialism, in other words, they will melt into social organizations and fuse with them. It is unreasonable to discuss the tendency of law towards withering away under capitalism.
Hiç yorum yok:
Yorum Gönder
Google hesabıyla yorum yapmak istemiyorsanız, yorum yazmadan önce Ad/Url seçeneğinde, sadece ad kısmını doldurabilirsiniz.